A Step-by-Step Guide to Editing The Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf
Below you can get an idea about how to edit and complete a Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf easily. Get started now.
- Push the“Get Form” Button below . Here you would be introduced into a splashboard that enables you to carry out edits on the document.
- Choose a tool you desire from the toolbar that pops up in the dashboard.
- After editing, double check and press the button Download.
- Don't hesistate to contact us via [email protected] for additional assistance.
The Most Powerful Tool to Edit and Complete The Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf


A Simple Manual to Edit Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf Online
Are you seeking to edit forms online? CocoDoc can assist you with its powerful PDF toolset. You can get it simply by opening any web brower. The whole process is easy and convenient. Check below to find out
- go to the PDF Editor Page.
- Upload a document you want to edit by clicking Choose File or simply dragging or dropping.
- Conduct the desired edits on your document with the toolbar on the top of the dashboard.
- Download the file once it is finalized .
Steps in Editing Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf on Windows
It's to find a default application which is able to help conduct edits to a PDF document. Fortunately CocoDoc has come to your rescue. Take a look at the Handback below to find out possible methods to edit PDF on your Windows system.
- Begin by acquiring CocoDoc application into your PC.
- Upload your PDF in the dashboard and make alterations on it with the toolbar listed above
- After double checking, download or save the document.
- There area also many other methods to edit your PDF for free, you can check this guide
A Step-by-Step Handbook in Editing a Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf on Mac
Thinking about how to edit PDF documents with your Mac? CocoDoc is ready to help you.. It empowers you to edit documents in multiple ways. Get started now
- Install CocoDoc onto your Mac device or go to the CocoDoc website with a Mac browser. Select PDF form from your Mac device. You can do so by clicking the tab Choose File, or by dropping or dragging. Edit the PDF document in the new dashboard which includes a full set of PDF tools. Save the file by downloading.
A Complete Handback in Editing Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf on G Suite
Intergating G Suite with PDF services is marvellous progess in technology, a blessing for you chop off your PDF editing process, making it quicker and with high efficiency. Make use of CocoDoc's G Suite integration now.
Editing PDF on G Suite is as easy as it can be
- Visit Google WorkPlace Marketplace and find out CocoDoc
- install the CocoDoc add-on into your Google account. Now you are able to edit documents.
- Select a file desired by pressing the tab Choose File and start editing.
- After making all necessary edits, download it into your device.
PDF Editor FAQ
What are harmonic systems in sociology?
Harmonic and Disharmonic Views of TrustLaurent Jaffrop. 11-26Harmonic and Disharmonic Views of TrustDo we need proof of others’ good will in order to act on our presumption of it? This question is at the crossroads of the practical and epistemic concepts of trust. Proof is, among other things, a ...https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.3401Abstract | Indice | Piano | Testo | Bibliografia | Note | Citazione | AutoreAbstractThis paper, at the crossroads of practical and epistemological questions, puts forward a non-standard approach to the study of a set of trust phenomena (trust, trustworthiness, distrust, self-trust, self-distrust…) and their interconnectedness. Two paradigmatic approaches to trust – harmonic and disharmonic – are unpacked and shown to be complementary. In contexts where the harmonic view applies, trust phenomena are mutually reinforcing. When the disharmonic view is appropriate, instead, they counterbalance one another. An analysis of Augustine’s De fide rerum quae non videntur helps introducing the former. Each view carries its own conception of the role of institutions in trust. For the harmonic approach, institutions are contexts that reinforce trust silently, whereas for the disharmonic view they are salient objects of trust. The need for an over-arching articulation of these limited views is further highlighted by appeal to another distinction, between background and decision-based forms of trust. This paves the way to what is here termed a metaharmonic theory of trust, a theory sensitive to the difference between the contexts where trust phenomena reinforce or counterbalance one another.Torna suTermini di indicizzazioneKeywords :trust, friendship, Augustine, coherence, beliefTorna suPiano1. The Augustinian paradigm2. Examples of applications of the Augustinian paradigm3. Completing the harmonic view with a disharmonic view of trustConcluding wordsTorna suTesto integralePDF 118kInvia tramite e-mail1Do we need proof of others’ good will in order to act on our presumption of it? This question is at the crossroads of the practical and epistemic concepts of trust. Proof is, among other things, a confirmation of that which would remain doubtful in its absence. In the epistemological debate, the sceptic believes that proof is required as long as prior trust does not guarantee validity. The anti-sceptic believes that this would be asking for proof that is superfluous or impossible. There is a certain parallel, as well as significant differences, between this discussion and the practical issues involved in trust, between the problems posed by faith and those posed by action and interaction. Epistemic trust is the credence given to information or the source of information, for example, someone’s word or our own faculties, such as memory or perception. Practical trust is a significant reduction in the uncertainty regarding the future actions of other agents.2An ambiguity must be dispelled: good will can be conceptualized as a simple absence of ill will or as a negative magnitude of it. When I complain that a shopkeeper does not demonstrate good will in response to my request as a customer, the good will I am expecting from him is just an absence of ill will. In what follows, since Augustine first addresses the issue of trust between friends, I will take the notion of good will in the sense of the negative magnitude of ill will. In other words, I will examine the issue of the proof of a positive volitive disposition, or benevolence, that goes beyond the ‘perhaps minimal’ good will whose presumption is characteristic of practical trust, according to Annette Baier (Baier 1986: 234).3What is the relationship between the problems of scepticism, to which some respond by mobilising trust in the domain of knowledge, and the problems of cooperation, to which some respond by mobilising trust in the domain of action? I propose that we approach this question on the basis of the opuscule De fide rerum quae non videntur (circa 400), which is attributed to Augustine. My reading will be neither scholarly nor historical, but retrospective, taking on the filter of current discussions on cooperation in the social sciences, on the one hand, and on coherentism in epistemology, on the other. A secondary undertaking is to suggest a distinction between the many roles of social institutions: they are not only a possible object of trust, but also provide a context that may or may not reinforce trust. In addition, social institutions can be subject to various forms or degrees of trust. For instance, trust with respect to a social institution can be very implicit, or much more explicit and even voluntary.4The methodology I have adopted consists in first developing a paradigm of trust, not based on how fides is treated in Augustine in general, but specifically on how it is handled in On Faith in Things Unseen. This paradigm of trust is one that is simultaneously epistemic and practical, and is a good fit for what I call a harmonic conception of trust. In the second part, I will argue that this model must be rendered more complete and complex by introducing another understanding of trust, the disharmonic conception, in order to account for other important aspects of the phenomena of trust.1. The Augustinian paradigm5The title of Augustine’s opuscule is redundant, since faith by definition is a type of trust whose object is that which cannot be seen. Believing has that which is invisible or absent as its object, while seeing in the figurative sense, just as in the literal sense, has that which is visible or present as its object. Seeing in the figurative sense is a type of cognition to which all cognition cannot be reduced. This is because there is another type of cognition – belief. There are obvious truths, which are blindingly obvious to the mind, and hidden truths, which are subject to faith.6Why this title? What is a pleonasm for Augustine is not one for the objector he is responding to. The objector, like Doubting Thomas, demands to see in order to believe. But this objection is based on a confusion, because if one needs to believe something, it is because one does not see it. In response, Augustine essentially develops epistemological considerations. He concludes by maintaining that at a higher degree of comprehension this faith, which in a preliminary analysis is not vision, is actually vision. Vision, whether it is intellectual or sensory, is then used as a metaphor for faith. There are ‘eyes of faith’ beyond bodily eyes and the eyes of the mind.7The most remarkable thing in Augustine’s analysis is that it runs into the practical problem of trust in interpersonal interactions, even if it is from afar. But these interactions are not really of the same nature as interaction in a large, complex society. Augustine talks about the practical problem of trust in a way that seems both exotic and stimulating to us. There is a distance between trust in family and friends as Augustine talks about it, which is linked to significant social institutions, and what we understand as trust today (perhaps since Hobbes? In any case, Hobbes contributed to this understanding). This distance makes it possible to bring out certain interesting aspects of the problem.8Augustine comes to this issue through the example of friendship. Friendship is a disposition that we do not see, and it is subject to fides, which is interchangeably faith and trust. He asks: What would happen if this trust in the other person’s disposition of friendship was absent in us? This may raise the issue, which is crucial in the social sciences, of the difference between the problems of cooperation in situations where you can adjust your actions because you are confident about the other person’s dispositions, and situations where you cannot do so because other people’s dispositions are hidden from you. In the latter situations, it is rational to adopt either, if available, the dominant strategy (that is, the strategy that yields a better payoff regardless of what the other chooses) or a Nash equilibrium (that is, a situation in which all chosen strategies are such that, taking into account the others’ strategies, each player gets the best payoff). This occurs most often because the behaviour we are expecting from others are actions that will be taken in the future, and observation of behaviour is our only means of knowing the dispositions of other agents. By having access to the other’s dispositions through fides, one gets a kind of assurance that the observation of behaviour cannot provide.9Augustine begins by recalling the truism that the domain of knowledge goes well beyond what we see with bodily eyes. Augustine takes the example closest to him: the operations of his own mind. Augustine knows that he is thinking, whereas this operation is invisible to bodily eyes. It is not invisible, however, to the eyes of the mind. “In our mind itself, whose nature is invisible, there are innumerable things” (Augustine 1950: 81). Augustine also takes the example of faith: When I believe, I know that I believe. This transparency of faith as an operation of the mind makes it so that when we believe, we cannot doubt that we believe (Chastaing 1956). Now, divine realities are of course inaccessible to bodily eyes, but they are no less inaccessible to the eyes of the mind. If they were subject to intellectual intuition, faith would be superfluous.10The model of self-knowledge is not sufficient to account for knowledge of divine realities. The problem of knowing divine realities is analogous to the problem of knowing other minds, and not to the problems of self-knowledge or knowledge of external, sensible realities. Augustine takes the analogy between access to the divine and access to the other literally. Hence the example of friendship, which is the interpersonal equivalent to faith in the divine.11Here is the problem: “Tell me, please, with what eyes do you see your friend’s disposition towards you? For no disposition can be seen with bodily eyes” (Augustine 1950: 83). ‘Disposition’ is a translation of voluntas. But the other person’s disposition is not perceptible to the eyes of my mind either. It is not present in my animus; I am not conscious of it. “If you do not see it, how do you on your part requite his loving kindness, if what you cannot see you do not believe?” (Augustine 1950: 83). Doubting Thomas’ requirement applied to social interactions would produce disastrous results. It is here that the epistemic issue of trust runs into the practical issue of cooperation. Since I do not see the other person’s good will towards me neither with the eyes of my mind nor with my bodily eyes, if I do not believe in this good will, then I will not return it.12Augustine’s pessimistic hypothesis evokes from afar the problem of how cooperation may emerge in a non-cooperative context through a tit-for-tat strategy. Robert Axelrod in The Evolution of Cooperation (1984) showed that the winning strategy in a repeated game would be for an agent to take the initiative to behave benevolently towards the partner in the first round, and then echo the other person’s response. But if the latter was not able to see the former’s benevolent conduct, then he could not respond with benevolent behaviour; or if he did respond benevolently, the former would not necessarily ‘see’ this behaviour as benevolent. In this case, benevolence could not be signalled, and thus crucial information is lacking, which results in a failure of cooperation. However, the connection between tit-for-tat and trustful conduct is superficial. For trust does not consist in observing the other’s behaviour, but in ‘seeing’ the other’s dispositions. Tit-for-tat is a case of mechanical generation of cooperation, whereas Augustinian ‘friendship’ rests upon built-in beliefs about other persons, rather than on our capacity to respond to behavioural outputs.13The fact is that we most often reward the other person’s benevolence by reciprocating. We play a different game than the prisoner’s dilemma. We view this benevolence with the eyes of faith. Reciprocation is evidence of trust in the other person’s disposition. Observable behaviour is subject to interpretation. Now, if benevolence and friendship were not present ab initio in interpersonal relationships, people could not interpret behaviour as demonstrating benevolence. “Your friend’s faith is not appreciated by you if there is in you no reciprocating faith by which you may believe that there is in him what you do not see” (Augustine 1950: 85).14The objector claims that he does not see the other’s friendship but recognizes it in his words and deeds. But in reality he believes; he trusts in his friend’s good will, but also in his friend’s reciprocal trust. Augustine rejects the argument that it would be enough to see benevolent words and deeds. There is a counter example on which Augustine bases his argument: I can see these words and deeds, and be mistaken. You can feign good will or hide ill will, “in expecting some advantage”. This is a strategy of deceit, which banks on the other person’s gullibility.15Augustine thus points out that you cannot have proof of the other person’s friendship by means that are completely external to the relationship of trust that binds the friends together. You cannot put the relationship of trust on hold while you find proof of your friendship:Indeed, since you wish to put faith in things not seen, ought not we, seeing that we do put faith in the heart of friends both when they have not been fully proven, and when we have proved them to be good by our misfortunes, even then we believe their good will toward us rather than see it? Unless it is that faith is so great that very appropriately we judge that we see (with the eyes of faith itself, as it were) what we believe, although we really ought to believe because we cannot see (Augustine 1950: 85‑7).1 This seems to agree with the empirical work of psychologists showing a mutual reinforcement over ti (...)16Proof does not prove this friendship for me unless I believe in this friendship. Proof is therefore superfluous and impossible anyway if it is understood as a means of taking us from a situation where we doubt the friendship to a situation of trust. If we do not initially believe in the friendship, we will not interpret signs or proof through the lens of trust as signs or proof of friendship. They may instead be construed as trickery. If the other person is not already ‘seen’ as a friend through the eyes of faith, proof will not work.117We must bear in mind that friendship, here, is a virtue. It refers to a superlative friendship, and not to a weak benevolence, like a disposition to cooperate. This is a significant difference from the cooperation problems modelled by non-cooperative games. If we replace this thick virtue – which occurs in a strong institutional, familial, or civic context – with a disposition to interact in a non-aggressive manner with unknown partners or outside of a significant institutional framework, Augustine’s words lose their relevance. The presumption of weak, minimal benevolence in the other person does not imply belief in his virtue, but only expectations regarding his behaviour.18The connection to the issue of practical trust is based on a thought experiment. Let us eliminate trust in the other person’s good will from interpersonal relationships. “Who will not mark what great disorder will result in them, and how dreadful a confusion will follow?” (Augustine 1950: 87). Augustine thus presents his imaginary world of widespread distrust as something that looks quite similar to the Hobbesian representation of the state of war.For who will be cherished by anyone in mutual charity, since love itself is invisible, if what I do not see I ought not to believe? Friendship, then, will completely perish, since it is established solely on mutual love (Augustine 1950: 87).19If friendship is absent, we cannot receive the other person’s marks of friendship since we cannot believe that he has given us marks of friendship. And if the other person’s actions are not interpreted as the actions of a friend, then the interaction will deteriorate accordingly. “If friendship perishes, the bonds of neither marriage nor of relationship nor of affinity will be held intact in the mind”. If spouses do not see one another’s love through the eyes of faith, they will not return the other’s love. Then their relationship cannot be friendship, i.e. reciprocal love. Similarly, children who do not know they are loved will not love their parents. Even beyond that, according to Augustine, all human relationships will be ruined in the absence of this belief.20In this thought experiment, it is not friendship that is presumed to be eliminated at the outset, but the belief in the other person’s love for us. Now, there cannot be friendship without faith in the other person’s love. The consequence of this initial elimination of belief is the deterioration or disappearance of friendship. Augustine thus illustrates what I describe in Section III as a harmonic conception of trust, according to which trust and trustworthiness reinforce one another. Similarly, self-trust and trust in the other person, practical trust and epistemic trust, trust and trust in trust also reinforce one another. According to this harmonic conception, when one part of this edifice deteriorates, the whole collapses.21Reciprocity in the relationship between A and B means that A sees B’s disposition to cooperate through the eyes of faith. If A does not see B’s cooperativeness, B will not reciprocate. What is Augustine’s position with respect to the following proposition, which I will introduce all the while accepting its anachronistic nature? Cooperation is based on a strategy of giving tit for tat, whether the behaviour is positive or negative. We imitate the other person’s response. In the beginning of the opuscule, when he talks about what is observable with bodily eyes or the eyes of the mind, Augustine considers that it is not true, in the context of friendship, that one person’s behaviour is adjusted on the basis of what he observes of the other’s behaviour. Now, if we consider Augustine’s final proposition, it would appear that friendly reciprocity is based on the vision of the other person’s love through the eyes of faith. If children do not see their parent’s love, they will not return their love. Within the institution of the family or friendship, there are only positive actions. We might be tempted to see a positive, virtuous form of tit-for-tat in the reciprocity of friendship.22This comparison is not absurd, since Augustine alludes to the situation of uncertainty when he considers the circumstances under which “charity is uncertain and affection (voluntas) suspected” (Augustine 1950: 87) between parents and children. However, we cannot really talk about a positive, virtuous version of tit-for-tat since this is the winning strategy in contexts where one does not cognitively have access to the other person’s dispositions. We match the other person’s behavioural response when we do not know his dispositions. It is difficult to talk about ‘tit-for-tat strategy’ in a situation where we have significant information that could reassure us about the other person’s dispositions. Friends view their friendship as an ‘assurance game’, rather than the application of a tit-for-tat rule to a repeated prisoner’s dilemma.23Let us sum up our initial findings:The profile of the interaction changes completely depending on whether we initially input belief in the other person’s love or suspicion regarding his dispositions.This analysis leads us to nuance the opposition between the practical problems of trust and the problems of evidence. These two types of issues converge in that they are both problems of seeing the invisible.Through his questioning on interpersonal fides, Augustine has thought, in his own way, about questions like ‘should we have trust in trust?’ or ‘does trust in the other presuppose self-trust?’. The operations of another mind, and a fortiori its dispositions, which cannot be an object of my vision through the eyes of my mind, can, however, be an object of my faith. I cannot trust the other person if I am not first confident in my abilities to see the other person’s love through the eyes of faith. If I doubt the other person’s love, then I will not see it. He who believes that seeing is believing cannot see anything in the sense that belief is a superior form of vision. The objector’s lack of trust in his own cognitive equipment could in practice lead him to not trust the other.This type of approach also draws attention to circularity in the edifice of trust. According to what I call a harmonic conception of trust, trust functions on a loop in line with the image of the ‘loop of trust’ used by Keith Lehrer (1997) in his defence of coherentist epistemology.2. Examples of applications of the Augustinian paradigm2 One example: Regarding physico-theological proof, the character Cleanthes in Hume’s Dialogues Conce (...)In the theological domain, this discussion shows an affinity with the debate on the status of proof in the case of God’s existence. This is not at all surprising since the example of the proof of friendship serves as a model for Augustine for the need for proof in religious matters. The question is whether this proof completely establishes trust or whether it at least partially presupposes a form of trust.2In the ethical domain, several authors, ancient as well as modern, have shown that an undertaking that claims that it is possible to define the meaning of moral predicates independently of and prior to their common understanding in everyday moral life is doomed to failure. Just like I cannot ‘see’ the other person’s goodness without being ‘a friend’ in the Augustinian sense, I cannot learn the meaning of the term ‘just’ in the moral sense fully in the absence of practical dispositions for ‘justice’. This point was particularly salient in the critique of theological voluntarism in the Cambridge Platonists, for example, and also in G.E. Moore’s critique of the naturalistic fallacy (Bouveresse 2016).In the epistemological domain too, trust cannot be found if it has been lost or put on hold, even if it is only long enough to obtain proof. Augustine’s words could apply to issues of modern scepticism in their epistemological as well as moral aspects. This theme is elaborated in Thomas Reid, for whom a natural capacity to trust is the principle behind both social experience and cognitive activities. Reid simultaneously maintains that “without fidelity and trust, there can be no human society” (Reid 2010: 334), and that “we are born under a necessity of trusting” our intellectual faculties (Reid 2010: 179-180). The reliability of our faculties does not need to be established by an additional loop, no more than practical trust in the other’s ‘good faith’ requires prior proof. This would be impossible anyway, according to the First Principle of Contingent Truths in the list of Principles of Common Sense: “That the natural faculties, by which we distinguish truth from error, are not fallacious. If any man should demand a proof of this, it is impossible to satisfy him”. Indeed, proof presupposes faith in this reliability (for a discussion of the interpretations of this principle, see Rysiew 2014).24According to Reid, since the attitudes or behaviours of trust cannot be wholly acquired, but rely on a natural capacity, it is fallacious and inappropriate to account for them in terms that are purely economic, prudential, or even purely moral:The things essential to human society, I mean good faith on the one part, and trust on the other, are formed by nature in the minds of children, before they are capable of knowing their utility, or being influenced by considerations either of duty or interest (Reid 2010: 335).3. Completing the harmonic view with a disharmonic view of trust25One important question is whether trust in other people and self-trust reinforce or counterbalance one another. Augustine claims that they reinforce one another. A second question is about the relationship between trust and distrust: are they opposites or complementary phenomena? Augustine, at least in his De fide rerum, claims that they are opposites. The Augustinian paradigm should be qualified on both points.26Indeed, there are forms of trust in other people, or institutions, which have their basis in self-distrust. People who do not trust themselves have recourse to coaches or counsellors, whom they trust. Professional therapists might be helpful, if friends or family members cannot do the job. In this Section, I try to understand the links between this kind of trust, on the one hand, and distrust, especially self-distrust, on the other.27Thus, I distinguish between two philosophical attitudes towards trust, ‘harmonic’ and ‘disharmonic’. The distinction arises when we ask whether one kind of trust combines well with other kinds, namely whether trust in others necessarily goes hand in hand with self-trust, and also whether trust necessarily accompanies trust in trust, or whether one kind of trust (say, epistemic trust) is necessarily associated with another kind (political trust, economic trust, or practical trust in general). According to the harmonic conception, the more (or less) you trust yourself, the more (or less) you trust others, and vice versa. According to the disharmonic conception, distrust towards other agents or institutions is congruent with trusting only oneself. Conversely, those who lack self-trust, in order to overcome their difficulties, may have to trust others, not others in general, but specific categories of people and perhaps determinate persons, in whom we place our trust either because of their personal qualities or because of their institutional role, or both.28Here is one argument in favour of the harmonic conception: Isabel trusts her own faculties and operations, including the operation of trusting other people. Thus, if Isabel trusts Margaret, Isabel’s self-trust reinforces her trust in Margaret. Conversely, were Isabel to suspect that her self-confidence was excessive, she would have reason to be more cautious in her relationship with Margaret. Also, if Isabel’s trust in Margaret was severely betrayed, then she would have reason not to trust her tendency to trust others.29However, in support of the disharmonic conception, I would reply: Isabel’s trust in Margaret may operate independently of Isabel’s self-trust, so that, if Isabel’s trust in Margaret was severely betrayed, Isabel could still (with some luck) count on herself. Conversely, were Isabel’s self-trust to become impaired, she (with some luck) could count on Margaret.30Let us consider another possible argument in favour of the harmonic conception, which goes like this: Trust and trustworthiness are causally and normatively dependent upon one another. The more someone is manifestly trustworthy, the more we trust that person. The more we trust someone, the more that person is encouraged to be trustworthy. Can someone who lacks self-trust be trustworthy? We might think that, were he trustworthy, he should be trustworthy for himself as well, and thus that he should trust himself. Yet he lacks self-trust. Therefore, he is not fully trustworthy. He is the rotten apple that spoils the barrel.31This argument, which I would not deem robust, is an argument against the compatibility between lack of self-trust – let us call it self-distrust – and mutual trust. It is not a relevant argument against the compatibility between self-distrust and one-way trust from the self-distrusting person in another person, for instance a therapist. Even though we suppose that self-distrusting people are thus not fully trustworthy, I do not see why this should hinder them from trusting someone else. Self-distrust might even motivate trust in specialists.32To sum up, according to the harmonic view, trust-tendency is a relationship that is symmetric in some sense and is also circular as far as the relationship between trust and self-trust is concerned:3 I use ‘symmetry’ in a loose sense. I thank Brian Jabarian and André Lapidus for their comments on t (...)Symmetry: If A tends to trust B, then B tends to be motivated to trust A.34 One proponent of the harmonic view is Keith Lehrer, who, in the wake of his coherentist interpretat (...)Circularity, interrelatedness of trust and self-trust: If A tends to trust B, then, A tends to trust herself; and if A trusts herself, she tends to trends B.433According to a strong version of the disharmonic view, trust-tendency is neither symmetric nor circular. Of course, it frequently happens that when A tends to trust B, B is motivated to trust A, etc. However, this does not rule out the significance of cases where it does not happen. This calls to mind prisoner’s dilemma games, where it is not rational to initiate trust, and it would appear to be rational not to respond to trust with trust. Moreover, there is often some sort of causal or motivational relationship between trust and self-distrust, or between distrust towards others and self-trust.34According to a weaker version of the disharmonic view – which I favour – trust-tendency is symmetric but not circular. If A tends to trust B, then B tends to be motivated to trust A. It would be imprudent to deny this, for this is just the way trust works. The view that trust-tendency is symmetric in this loose sense suggests that trust is a solution that is quite different from the dominant strategy in a prisoner’s dilemma, and that the parties are playing a different game, corresponding to one option in Amartya Sen’s assurance game: the hypothesis that “everyone has implicit faith in everyone else doing the ‘right thing’” (Sen 1967: 114). There are particular practical and institutional contexts in which the phenomenon of trust appears: The agents’ conduct is constrained by rules, habits, and institutional contexts, which diminish uncertainty and turn it into an acceptable risk. In these contexts, there is a causal and normative, or motivational, relationship between A’s tendency to trust B, and B’s tendency to trust A. The fact remains that trust-tendency is not circular in the above sense: As in the strong disharmonic conception, there is often some sort of causal or motivational relationship between trust and self-distrust, etc.35This comparison between harmonic and disharmonic views of trust should take into account the distinction between background implicit trust and trust as an action. The harmonic conception draws heavily on background trust, whereas, in accordance with the disharmonic conception, trust as an intentional and voluntary behaviour remains a convenient recourse for those who lack self-trust. However, this distinction and the latter distinction between the two views of trust cannot be exactly aligned. Moreover, implicitness, voluntariness, etc. differ in degree as well as in kind.5 Annette Baier interestingly notes that “we inhabit a climate of trust as we inhabit an atmosphere a (...)36Background trust cannot be willed. It is deeply involuntary; it is not something we decide to do; it is the state of our relationships with people, environments, or the natural world, from which doubt or suspicion is absent. Whereas mistrust forms the background to a decision to trust, insofar as it involves an awareness of uncertainty, a primitive state of trust is the background to our experience of distrust: For instance, as a result of an accident, I discover that I should not trust my legs, although until now I had trusted them, while not even being conscious of my trusting them – a case of ‘atmospheric’ trust.537Let us modify the example in order to tackle the question of epistemic self-trust. Let us substitute ‘legs’ with ‘mental faculties’. Thus, we may distinguish two kinds of epistemic self-trust:(Background trust) I have no reason at all to doubt that my mental faculties will allow me to correctly think, talk, argue, feel, perceive, judge, love, etc. It is not only the case that I have no reason to suspect my mental faculties: I am not even aware of it. It did not even occur to me that I have no reason, etc.(Trust as an action) I have reason to think that my mental faculties are fallible; in spite of that, I place my trust in them, for I have an even better reason to do so.38In this shift from bodily to mental faculties, we may observe an analogy between distrust and scepticism. This debate took centre stage in 18th century Scottish philosophy. Both David Hume (the sceptic) and Thomas Reid (the anti-sceptic) claimed that there are irresistible natural beliefs, for instance the belief in the existence of external objects beyond our perceptions, which even sceptical philosophers cannot help having. Thus, we could speak of an epistemic background trust in the existence of objects or persons. One difference between David Hume and Thomas Reid is that the former considers that this background trust ought to be justified, and yet cannot be justified; whereas the latter replies that epistemic trust does not need to be justified. According to the Humean sceptic, our faculties are so fallible that we should be very careful in their use. Nevertheless, in everyday life, we act upon the premise that they are trustworthy.39Until now, I have set out the rudiments of a philosophy of trust from a few (too) simple examples: legs, bodily faculties, and mental faculties are not agents. A fuller philosophy of trust needs to focus on the interactions between agents. An agent, roughly speaking, is at the centre of intentions, and thus a centre of will and intelligence. Were my legs or my faculties agents, then trusting them would look completely different. For then my legs or my faculties could decide to respond or not to my expectations towards them. I would not be able to know in advance what they are about to do, not only because of the intrinsic uncertainty of future events, but also because of the uncertainty that is characteristic of agency.40When the context of interactions between agents is characterised by their acute awareness of uncertainty and risk – and thus may encourage distrust – trust as an action (Dumouchel 2005) is an option. The difference between trust and distrust, here, lies not in the informational input, but in the practical output. The informational input is a diagnosis of uncertainty. This diagnosis may lead to the option of defection: We prefer not to expose ourselves to a betrayal of trust. It is thus a case of practical distrust. The same diagnosis may lead to the option of participation: We accept the risk of exposing ourselves to betrayal in order to pave the way for cooperation. It is thus a case of practical trust. Here the voluntary nature of this form of trust is fully manifest: The only difference between trust and distrust in this situation is between the decision to escape and the decision to accept the possibility of being let down. They converge in the initial analysis and diverge in the resulting action. The difference between the two is behavioural.6 Let us note in passing that a loop between the voluntary and the involuntary kinds of trust is plau (...)41If we turn now to atmospheric trust, the picture is quite different. This kind of trust does not differ from distrust only as a practical output of the same informational input. Background trust is at least the absence of distrust, and perhaps the opposite of distrust. The awareness of uncertainty is numbed. By what? It would be a gross mistake to answer: by trust. Trust is the explanandum, not the explanans. However, it is true that there is a phenomenon of self-reinforcement behind it, since experience, customs, practices, conventions, and institutions play a crucial role in the formation of background trust. (a) Habit is the process through which we learn both to respond to the environment and to become familiar with specific responses of the environment. Once we are accustomed to a state of affairs, we do not pay attention to difficulties as long as our expectations are not significantly disappointed; we even tolerate exceptions, failures, or mistakes. (b) Conventions may be viewed in a Humean way as having positive feedback on the mutual adjustment from which they proceed. (c) Institutions are contexts, which diminish the uncertainty of social interactions, because they may constitute sufficient conditions for what Bernard Williams (1988) calls thick trust.642Since Augustine’s thesis is about a world of virtue, friendship, and faith, whereas the disharmonic view fits in with a world of weakness and wariness, they do not contradict one another. The two theses may even be compatible if one world coexists with the other.7 Self-trust may be seen as a necessary condition for minimal procedural autonomy, understood as the (...)43One reason why I put forward the distinction between harmonic and disharmonic views is that it highlights the controversy on the status and scope of practical autonomy. The harmonic conception encourages a high idea of self-control, in which autonomy and sociality are mutually integrated.7 On the contrary, the disharmonic conception fosters a more modest view of self-control, tailored to the fact of our weakness. In this latter conception – a form of self-paternalism – self-control is indirect and draws on the recourse to counsellors, pastors, etc., determinate persons, roles, or institutions.44Let us imagine the situation of agents who could not trust themselves and who would also be aware of being disloyal to themselves as well as to others, unable to stick to their commitments, and thus so unreliable that nobody could trust them. In a word, these agents would add complete lack of self-confidence to utter untrustworthiness. Would they be also untrusting, unable to trust others? Not necessarily, according to the disharmonic conception.45These constitutively weak agents are not so different from us. What I call a ‘hopeless case’ is not the effect of practical irrationality only, understood as an accident or as a particular pathology. It is the consequence of a bundle of common circumstances, which notably include bad luck and the temporal structure of human existence. The sense of the uncertainty of our own future actions, together with the experience of our past failures, may be sufficient to convince us that we are unreliable for ourselves as well as for others. Here distrust is not just the shadow of trust – a negative solution to the practical problem to which trust is the positive solution – but the feeling that trust as well as trustworthiness are out of reach.46A solution comes from the resources of human psychology, with some help from the others. As Edward Hinchman puts it: “The diachronic exercise of practical reason is […] based on trust – typically on self-trust, but when self-trust fails […] it will have to be based on trust in others” (Hinchman 2003: 26). In this hopeless case, trust as an action is the correct option and is directed at a particular ‘trustee’, therapist, expert or coach. Since it is voluntary, it is something we can do even though atmospheric trust is lacking, and in the absence of evidence of trustworthiness. As Paul Dumouchel argues:Viewing trust as an action suggests that what makes trust necessary is not so much our lack of knowledge about the world as the fact that we depend upon each other. It is true that we do not have perfect knowledge of the world, but even if I did know in advance what you will do, it does not follow that I could always avoid giving you power over me.47Indeed, background trust, whether interpersonal or organisational or both, is also involved in people’s relationships with their therapists. Nevertheless, in hopeless cases, automatic respect for institutional authorities or for the person is not sufficient or does not work. Here trust as an action is of great use. Even though background trust plays a major role in epistemic behaviours, including those that involve recourse to the expertise of others, trust in the expertise of others, at least when it has a therapeutic or perhaps a religious dimension, is often a decision, the beginning of an action. However, my argument for the practical significance of the judicious placing of trust is anything but an encomium for sheer voluntarism, nor is it akin to highly demanding views of personal autonomy. On the contrary, my intention is to point out that when distrust, including self-distrust, is pervasive, some kind of trust is still present, and remains a technical resource that is well suited to our condition of weakness.Concluding words8 See for instance the beginning of Book VIII of the Confessions, where a still weak Augustine finds (...)48In the first part of this paper, I have set out the Augustinian paradigm of trust. In the second part, I have brought a different, disharmonic, conception of trust into the discussion. This seems to suggest that Augustine embodies a harmonic understanding of trust, which is highly debatable. Out of consideration for Augustine and especially for his Confessions, I must say that his insistence on the Fall and the need for God’s grace and the help of others would plead in favour of a disharmonic view. The harmonic view applies to the realm of the faithful. We need the disharmonic view to account for the rest of us, including Augustine before his full conversion.849Should we consider the two views to be incompatible? No. They are two parts of a more comprehensive view (which, were it not pompous, I would term metaharmonic) that accounts for the dynamic of trust in contexts where the phenomena of trust reinforce one another, as well as in contexts where they counterbalance one another. Institutions are often a source of trust: This is correctly described by the disharmonic view. The harmonic view captures the fact that institutions are also the object of implicit trust. It also accounts for the way in which institutions may warrant and reinforce implicit trust. In brief, the two views are complementary.9 See Knud Ejler Løgstrup (1997: 8) about the way in which trust in relatives and friends sets the pa (...)10 Portions of this paper have presented and discussed on four occasions: at the seminar Les Après-mid (...)50A remaining question is which view has priority over the other. Although a more in-depth argument would require more space than can be allotted to it here, I think that the harmonic conception, because it concerns the natural core of trust, which guides further acquisition and development of trust skills,9 is conceptually central, and the disharmonic, peripheral. However, the philosophy of trust should not neglect the periphery.10Torna suBibliografiaDOI are automaticaly added to references by Bilbo, OpenEdition's Bibliographic Annotation Tool.Users of institutions which have subscribed to one of OpenEdition freemium programs can download references for which Bilbo found a DOI in standard formats using the buttons available on the right.Augustine, 1950, De Fide Rerum quae non videntur, in M.F. McDonald (ed. and trans.), Washington D.C., The Catholic University of America Press.Axelrod, R., 1984, The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books.DOI : 10.1126/science.7466396Baier, A., 1986, Trust and antitrust, “Ethics”, 96, 2: 231-260.Bouveresse, J., 2017, Éthique et logique: Cudworth, Leibniz, Moore et la critique du ‘sophisme volontariste’, in M. Pécharman and P. de Rouilhan (eds), Le philosophe et le langage. Études offertes à Jean-Claude Pariente, Paris, Vrin: 275-302.Chastaing, M., 1956, Consciousness and evidence, “Mind”, 65, 259: 346-358.Dumouchel, P., 2005, Trust as an action, “European Journal of Sociology”, 46, 3: 417-428.DOI : 10.1017/S0003975605000160Govier, T., 1993, Self-trust, autonomy, and self-esteem, “Hypathia”, 8, 1: 99-120.Hinchman, E., 2003, Trust and diachronic agency, “Noüs”, 37, 1: 25-51.Jaffro, L., 2009, Ist die Evidenz der Existenz des Anderen ein Modell für die Gotteserkenntnis? Berkeley, Hume, Reid und das ‘Argument des Irregulären’, “Aufklärung. Interdisziplinäres Jahrbuch zur Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts und seiner Wirkungsgeschichte”, 21: 51-74.Lehrer, K., 1997, Self-Trust. A Study of Reason, Knowledge, and Autonomy, New York, Oxford University Press.DOI : 10.2307/2653569Løgstrup, K., 1997, The ethical demand, H. Fink, A. MacIntyre (eds), Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press.Miller, P., Rempel, J., 2004, Trust and partner-enhancing attributions in close relationships, “Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin”, 30, 6: 695-705.DOI : 10.1177/0146167203262803Reid, T., 2010, Essays on the active powers of man, in K. Haakonssen, J.A. Harris (eds), Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press.Rysiew, P., 2014, Reid’s First Principle, “Canadian Journal of Philosophy”, 41, S1: 167-182.Sen, A., 1967, Isolation, assurance, and the social rate of discount, “The Quarterly Journal of Economics”, 81, 1: 112-124.DOI : 10.2307/1879675Weckert, J., 2005, Trust in cyberspace, in R. Cavalier (ed.), The Impact of the Internet on Our Moral Lives, Albany, State University of New York Press: 95-117.Williams, B., 1995, Formal structure and social reality, in B. Williams, Making Sense of Humanity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 111-122.Torna suNote1 This seems to agree with the empirical work of psychologists showing a mutual reinforcement over time between a feeling of trust and a favourable interpretation of the partner’s motivations in married couples (Miller, Rempel 2004). This type of approach bolsters the conception that trust is a ‘seeing-as’, which is in line with Augustine’s paradigm: “If A sees B as trustworthy (with respect to A), he interprets B’s behavior as showing goodwill, or at least not ill will, toward A. If A sees B as untrustworthy, that is, A distrusts B as opposed to having no views on the matter, he interprets B’s behavior as showing ill will toward A (a typical characteristic of the paranoid A)” (Weckert 2005: 103). According to John Weckert, the disappearance of trust is a ‘gestalt switch’ (105).2 One example: Regarding physico-theological proof, the character Cleanthes in Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Part III) calls an argument that is distinct from reasoning by analogy an ‘irregular argument’. An irregular argument, which is epistemological in nature, consists in demonstrating that belief in an intelligent cause of the universe is irresistible, as is our trust in the existence of others. This irregular argument is considered to be valid by authors such as Berkeley and Reid (Jaffro 2009).3 I use ‘symmetry’ in a loose sense. I thank Brian Jabarian and André Lapidus for their comments on the properties of trust-tendency.4 One proponent of the harmonic view is Keith Lehrer, who, in the wake of his coherentist interpretation of Thomas Reid and the Reidian stance in his own epistemological work, claims that there is a “keystone loop of self-trust, trust of others, and the trustworthiness of ourselves and others for ourselves and others” (Lehrer 1997: 126).5 Annette Baier interestingly notes that “we inhabit a climate of trust as we inhabit an atmosphere and notice it as we notice air, only when it becomes scarce or polluted” (Baier 1986: 234).6 Let us note in passing that a loop between the voluntary and the involuntary kinds of trust is plausible: The initial decision to trust, like a Pascalian wager, with some luck may foster habitual trust as ‘second nature’; conversely, background trust, encouraged by social conventions and practices, may facilitate the decision to trust in a context where uncertainty resurfaces.7 Self-trust may be seen as a necessary condition for minimal procedural autonomy, understood as the ability to think and decide for oneself (Govier 1993).8 See for instance the beginning of Book VIII of the Confessions, where a still weak Augustine finds help and support from Simplicianus.9 See Knud Ejler Løgstrup (1997: 8) about the way in which trust in relatives and friends sets the pattern for trust in outsiders, contrary to the common view that suggests that mistrust is the only option beyond the circle of acquaintance: “Under normal circumstances […] we accept the stranger’s word and do not mistrust him until we have some particular reason to do so. We never suspect a person of falsehood until after we have caught him in a lie”. The intimate connection between epistemic and practical trust is obvious here.10 Portions of this paper have presented and discussed on four occasions: at the seminar Les Après-midis de Philosophie et Economie in Paris (December 2017); before the Société de Philosophy du Québec (May 2017); at the Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes (December 2015); at the Philosophy Department of the University of Nanjing (April 2014). I thank the organisers and participants for their comments. The paper especially benefited from conversations with Jacopo Domenicucci, André Lapidus, Aude Bandini and Brian Jabarian.Following is the link for newly created space for getting all Indian government jobs updates. Because many students say that they missed to fill the form and now the time has gone. So, let me remind you in a proper time about the jobs, it’s all description, providing link for main website to fill this form, sending link for videos that how to fill this form. So, follow this newly created space and this space is managing from the student of Banaras Hindu University.Link…
What just happened in America?
This is a really complicated question to answer. There are a number of things that we can look at and say the Democrats did wrong and the Republicans did wrong. We can do a lot of finger pointing. To me however, there is one defining thing that explains the most. Just prior to becoming confirmed as Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court justice to be, Nixon appointee to SCOTUS, Lewis Powell wrote a memo to the U.S. Chamber of Commerce. This memo became the manifesto for the conservatives in the business community urging them to take control of both political parties, the education system, and the media. The U.S. Chamber of Commerce saw to it, and later Congress and the Supreme court saw to it that all recommendations of the Powell memo were implemented. This new conservative agenda completely replaced the Republican agenda championed by Eisenhower And so the dumbing down the U.S. population through the education system and the media began in earnest leading the U.S. inexorably to a Trump presidency. After reading the memo, please checkout the link to a PDF on follow ups to this memo by the Chamber of Commerce, particularly the memo about cracking the news media:Confidential Memorandum: Attack of American Free Enterprise SystemDATE: August 23, 1971TO: Mr. Eugene B. Sydnor, Jr., Chairman, Education Committee, U.S. Chamber of CommerceFROM: Lewis F. Powell, Jr.This memorandum is submitted at your request as a basis for the discussion on August 24 with Mr. Booth (executive vice president) and others at the U.S. Chamber of Commerce. The purpose is to identify the problem, and suggest possible avenues of action for further consideration.Dimensions of the AttackNo thoughtful person can question that the American economic system is under broad attack. This varies in scope, intensity, in the techniques employed, and in the level of visibility.There always have been some who opposed the American system, and preferred socialism or some form of statism (communism or fascism). Also, there always have been critics of the system, whose criticism has been wholesome and constructive so long as the objective was to improve rather than to subvert or destroy.But what now concerns us is quite new in the history of America. We are not dealing with sporadic or isolated attacks from a relatively few extremists or even from the minority socialist cadre. Rather, the assault on the enterprise system is broadly based and consistently pursued. It is gaining momentum and converts.Sources of the AttackThe sources are varied and diffused. They include, not unexpectedly, the Communists, New Leftists and other revolutionaries who would destroy the entire system, both political and economic. These extremists of the left are far more numerous, better financed, and increasingly are more welcomed and encouraged by other elements of society, than ever before in our history. But they remain a small minority, and are not yet the principal cause for concern.The most disquieting voices joining the chorus of criticism come from perfectly respectable elements of society: from the college campus, the pulpit, the media, the intellectual and literary journals, the arts and sciences, and from politicians. In most of these groups the movement against the system is participated in only by minorities. Yet, these often are the most articulate, the most vocal, the most prolific in their writing and speaking.Moreover, much of the media-for varying motives and in varying degrees-either voluntarily accords unique publicity to these “attackers,” or at least allows them to exploit the media for their purposes. This is especially true of television, which now plays such a predominant role in shaping the thinking, attitudes and emotions of our people.One of the bewildering paradoxes of our time is the extent to which the enterprise system tolerates, if not participates in, its own destruction.The campuses from which much of the criticism emanates are supported by (i) tax funds generated largely from American business, and (ii) contributions from capital funds controlled or generated by American business. The boards of trustees of our universities overwhelmingly are composed of men and women who are leaders in the system.Most of the media, including the national TV systems, are owned and theoretically controlled by corporations which depend upon profits, and the enterprise system to survive.Tone of the AttackThis memorandum is not the place to document in detail the tone, character, or intensity of the attack. The following quotations will suffice to give one a general idea:William Kunstler, warmly welcomed on campuses and listed in a recent student poll as the “American lawyer most admired,” incites audiences as follows:“You must learn to fight in the streets, to revolt, to shoot guns. We will learn to do all of the things that property owners fear.”2 The New Leftists who heed Kunstler’s advice increasingly are beginning to act — not just against military recruiting offices and manufacturers of munitions, but against a variety of businesses: “Since February, 1970, branches (of Bank of America) have been attacked 39 times, 22 times with explosive devices and 17 times with fire bombs or by arsonists.”3 Although New Leftist spokesmen are succeeding in radicalizing thousands of the young, the greater cause for concern is the hostility of respectable liberals and social reformers. It is the sum total of their views and influence which could indeed fatally weaken or destroy the system.A chilling description of what is being taught on many of our campuses was written by Stewart Alsop:“Yale, like every other major college, is graduating scores of bright young men who are practitioners of ‘the politics of despair.’ These young men despise the American political and economic system . . . (their) minds seem to be wholly closed. They live, not by rational discussion, but by mindless slogans.”4 A recent poll of students on 12 representative campuses reported that: “Almost half the students favored socialization of basic U.S. industries.”5A visiting professor from England at Rockford College gave a series of lectures entitled “The Ideological War Against Western Society,” in which he documents the extent to which members of the intellectual community are waging ideological warfare against the enterprise system and the values of western society. In a foreword to these lectures, famed Dr. Milton Friedman of Chicago warned: “It (is) crystal clear that the foundations of our free society are under wide-ranging and powerful attack — not by Communist or any other conspiracy but by misguided individuals parroting one another and unwittingly serving ends they would never intentionally promote.”6Perhaps the single most effective antagonist of American business is Ralph Nader, who — thanks largely to the media — has become a legend in his own time and an idol of millions of Americans. A recent article in Fortune speaks of Nader as follows:“The passion that rules in him — and he is a passionate man — is aimed at smashing utterly the target of his hatred, which is corporate power. He thinks, and says quite bluntly, that a great many corporate executives belong in prison — for defrauding the consumer with shoddy merchandise, poisoning the food supply with chemical additives, and willfully manufacturing unsafe products that will maim or kill the buyer. He emphasizes that he is not talking just about ‘fly-by-night hucksters’ but the top management of blue chip business.”7A frontal assault was made on our government, our system of justice, and the free enterprise system by Yale Professor Charles Reich in his widely publicized book: “The Greening of America,” published last winter.The foregoing references illustrate the broad, shotgun attack on the system itself. There are countless examples of rifle shots which undermine confidence and confuse the public. Favorite current targets are proposals for tax incentives through changes in depreciation rates and investment credits. These are usually described in the media as “tax breaks,” “loop holes” or “tax benefits” for the benefit of business. As viewed by a columnist in the Post, such tax measures would benefit “only the rich, the owners of big companies.”8It is dismaying that many politicians make the same argument that tax measures of this kind benefit only “business,” without benefit to “the poor.” The fact that this is either political demagoguery or economic illiteracy is of slight comfort. This setting of the “rich” against the “poor,” of business against the people, is the cheapest and most dangerous kind of politics.The Apathy and Default of BusinessWhat has been the response of business to this massive assault upon its fundamental economics, upon its philosophy, upon its right to continue to manage its own affairs, and indeed upon its integrity?The painfully sad truth is that business, including the boards of directors’ and the top executives of corporations great and small and business organizations at all levels, often have responded — if at all — by appeasement, ineptitude and ignoring the problem. There are, of course, many exceptions to this sweeping generalization. But the net effect of such response as has been made is scarcely visible.In all fairness, it must be recognized that businessmen have not been trained or equipped to conduct guerrilla warfare with those who propagandize against the system, seeking insidiously and constantly to sabotage it. The traditional role of business executives has been to manage, to produce, to sell, to create jobs, to make profits, to improve the standard of living, to be community leaders, to serve on charitable and educational boards, and generally to be good citizens. They have performed these tasks very well indeed.But they have shown little stomach for hard-nose contest with their critics, and little skill in effective intellectual and philosophical debate.A column recently carried by the Wall Street Journal was entitled: “Memo to GM: Why Not Fight Back?”9 Although addressed to GM by name, the article was a warning to all American business. Columnist St. John said:“General Motors, like American business in general, is ‘plainly in trouble’ because intellectual bromides have been substituted for a sound intellectual exposition of its point of view.” Mr. St. John then commented on the tendency of business leaders to compromise with and appease critics. He cited the concessions which Nader wins from management, and spoke of “the fallacious view many businessmen take toward their critics.” He drew a parallel to the mistaken tactics of many college administrators: “College administrators learned too late that such appeasement serves to destroy free speech, academic freedom and genuine scholarship. One campus radical demand was conceded by university heads only to be followed by a fresh crop which soon escalated to what amounted to a demand for outright surrender.”One need not agree entirely with Mr. St. John’s analysis. But most observers of the American scene will agree that the essence of his message is sound. American business “plainly in trouble”; the response to the wide range of critics has been ineffective, and has included appeasement; the time has come — indeed, it is long overdue — for the wisdom, ingenuity and resources of American business to be marshalled against those who would destroy it.Responsibility of Business ExecutivesWhat specifically should be done? The first essential — a prerequisite to any effective action — is for businessmen to confront this problem as a primary responsibility of corporate management.The overriding first need is for businessmen to recognize that the ultimate issue may be survival — survival of what we call the free enterprise system, and all that this means for the strength and prosperity of America and the freedom of our people.The day is long past when the chief executive officer of a major corporation discharges his responsibility by maintaining a satisfactory growth of profits, with due regard to the corporation’s public and social responsibilities. If our system is to survive, top management must be equally concerned with protecting and preserving the system itself. This involves far more than an increased emphasis on “public relations” or “governmental affairs” — two areas in which corporations long have invested substantial sums.A significant first step by individual corporations could well be the designation of an executive vice president (ranking with other executive VP’s) whose responsibility is to counter-on the broadest front-the attack on the enterprise system. The public relations department could be one of the foundations assigned to this executive, but his responsibilities should encompass some of the types of activities referred to subsequently in this memorandum. His budget and staff should be adequate to the task.Possible Role of the Chamber of CommerceBut independent and uncoordinated activity by individual corporations, as important as this is, will not be sufficient. Strength lies in organization, in careful long-range planning and implementation, in consistency of action over an indefinite period of years, in the scale of financing available only through joint effort, and in the political power available only through united action and national organizations.Moreover, there is the quite understandable reluctance on the part of any one corporation to get too far out in front and to make itself too visible a target.The role of the National Chamber of Commerce is therefore vital. Other national organizations (especially those of various industrial and commercial groups) should join in the effort, but no other organizations appear to be as well situated as the Chamber. It enjoys a strategic position, with a fine reputation and a broad base of support. Also — and this is of immeasurable merit — there are hundreds of local Chambers of Commerce which can play a vital supportive role.It hardly need be said that before embarking upon any program, the Chamber should study and analyze possible courses of action and activities, weighing risks against probable effectiveness and feasibility of each. Considerations of cost, the assurance of financial and other support from members, adequacy of staffing and similar problems will all require the most thoughtful consideration.The CampusThe assault on the enterprise system was not mounted in a few months. It has gradually evolved over the past two decades, barely perceptible in its origins and benefiting (sic) from a gradualism that provoked little awareness much less any real reaction.Although origins, sources and causes are complex and interrelated, and obviously difficult to identify without careful qualification, there is reason to believe that the campus is the single most dynamic source. The social science faculties usually include members who are unsympathetic to the enterprise system. They may range from a Herbert Marcuse, Marxist faculty member at the University of California at San Diego, and convinced socialists, to the ambivalent liberal critic who finds more to condemn than to commend. Such faculty members need not be in a majority. They are often personally attractive and magnetic; they are stimulating teachers, and their controversy attracts student following; they are prolific writers and lecturers; they author many of the textbooks, and they exert enormous influence — far out of proportion to their numbers — on their colleagues and in the academic world.Social science faculties (the political scientist, economist, sociologist and many of the historians) tend to be liberally oriented, even when leftists are not present. This is not a criticism per se, as the need for liberal thought is essential to a balanced viewpoint. The difficulty is that “balance” is conspicuous by its absence on many campuses, with relatively few members being of conservatives or moderate persuasion and even the relatively few often being less articulate and aggressive than their crusading colleagues.This situation extending back many years and with the imbalance gradually worsening, has had an enormous impact on millions of young American students. In an article in Barron’s Weekly, seeking an answer to why so many young people are disaffected even to the point of being revolutionaries, it was said: “Because they were taught that way.”10 Or, as noted by columnist Stewart Alsop, writing about his alma mater: “Yale, like every other major college, is graduating scores’ of bright young men … who despise the American political and economic system.”As these “bright young men,” from campuses across the country, seek opportunities to change a system which they have been taught to distrust — if not, indeed “despise” — they seek employment in the centers of the real power and influence in our country, namely: (i) with the news media, especially television; (ii) in government, as “staffers” and consultants at various levels; (iii) in elective politics; (iv) as lecturers and writers, and (v) on the faculties at various levels of education.Many do enter the enterprise system — in business and the professions — and for the most part they quickly discover the fallacies of what they have been taught. But those who eschew the mainstream of the system often remain in key positions of influence where they mold public opinion and often shape governmental action. In many instances, these “intellectuals” end up in regulatory agencies or governmental departments with large authority over the business system they do not believe in.If the foregoing analysis is approximately sound, a priority task of business — and organizations such as the Chamber — is to address the campus origin of this hostility. Few things are more sanctified in American life than academic freedom. It would be fatal to attack this as a principle. But if academic freedom is to retain the qualities of “openness,” “fairness” and “balance” — which are essential to its intellectual significance — there is a great opportunity for constructive action. The thrust of such action must be to restore the qualities just mentioned to the academic communities.What Can Be Done About the CampusThe ultimate responsibility for intellectual integrity on the campus must remain on the administrations and faculties of our colleges and universities. But organizations such as the Chamber can assist and activate constructive change in many ways, including the following:Staff of ScholarsThe Chamber should consider establishing a staff of highly qualified scholars in the social sciences who do believe in the system. It should include several of national reputation whose authorship would be widely respected — even when disagreed with.Staff of SpeakersThere also should be a staff of speakers of the highest competency. These might include the scholars, and certainly those who speak for the Chamber would have to articulate the product of the scholars.Speaker’s BureauIn addition to full-time staff personnel, the Chamber should have a Speaker’s Bureau which should include the ablest and most effective advocates from the top echelons of American business.Evaluation of TextbooksThe staff of scholars (or preferably a panel of independent scholars) should evaluate social science textbooks, especially in economics, political science and sociology. This should be a continuing program.The objective of such evaluation should be oriented toward restoring the balance essential to genuine academic freedom. This would include assurance of fair and factual treatment of our system of government and our enterprise system, its accomplishments, its basic relationship to individual rights and freedoms, and comparisons with the systems of socialism, fascism and communism. Most of the existing textbooks have some sort of comparisons, but many are superficial, biased and unfair.We have seen the civil rights movement insist on re-writing many of the textbooks in our universities and schools. The labor unions likewise insist that textbooks be fair to the viewpoints of organized labor. Other interested citizens groups have not hesitated to review, analyze and criticize textbooks and teaching materials. In a democratic society, this can be a constructive process and should be regarded as an aid to genuine academic freedom and not as an intrusion upon it.If the authors, publishers and users of textbooks know that they will be subjected — honestly, fairly and thoroughly — to review and critique by eminent scholars who believe in the American system, a return to a more rational balance can be expected.Equal Time on the CampusThe Chamber should insist upon equal time on the college speaking circuit. The FBI publishes each year a list of speeches made on college campuses by avowed Communists. The number in 1970 exceeded 100. There were, of course, many hundreds of appearances by leftists and ultra liberals who urge the types of viewpoints indicated earlier in this memorandum. There was no corresponding representation of American business, or indeed by individuals or organizations who appeared in support of the American system of government and business.Every campus has its formal and informal groups which invite speakers. Each law school does the same thing. Many universities and colleges officially sponsor lecture and speaking programs. We all know the inadequacy of the representation of business in the programs.It will be said that few invitations would be extended to Chamber speakers.11 This undoubtedly would be true unless the Chamber aggressively insisted upon the right to be heard — in effect, insisted upon “equal time.” University administrators and the great majority of student groups and committees would not welcome being put in the position publicly of refusing a forum to diverse views, indeed, this is the classic excuse for allowing Communists to speak.The two essential ingredients are (i) to have attractive, articulate and well-informed speakers; and (ii) to exert whatever degree of pressure — publicly and privately — may be necessary to assure opportunities to speak. The objective always must be to inform and enlighten, and not merely to propagandize.Balancing of FacultiesPerhaps the most fundamental problem is the imbalance of many faculties. Correcting this is indeed a long-range and difficult project. Yet, it should be undertaken as a part of an overall program. This would mean the urging of the need for faculty balance upon university administrators and boards of trustees.The methods to be employed require careful thought, and the obvious pitfalls must be avoided. Improper pressure would be counterproductive. But the basic concepts of balance, fairness and truth are difficult to resist, if properly presented to boards of trustees, by writing and speaking, and by appeals to alumni associations and groups.This is a long road and not one for the fainthearted. But if pursued with integrity and conviction it could lead to a strengthening of both academic freedom on the campus and of the values which have made America the most productive of all societies.Graduate Schools of BusinessThe Chamber should enjoy a particular rapport with the increasingly influential graduate schools of business. Much that has been suggested above applies to such schools.Should not the Chamber also request specific courses in such schools dealing with the entire scope of the problem addressed by this memorandum? This is now essential training for the executives of the future.Secondary EducationWhile the first priority should be at the college level, the trends mentioned above are increasingly evidenced in the high schools. Action programs, tailored to the high schools and similar to those mentioned, should be considered. The implementation thereof could become a major program for local chambers of commerce, although the control and direction — especially the quality control — should be retained by the National Chamber.What Can Be Done About the Public?Reaching the campus and the secondary schools is vital for the long-term. Reaching the public generally may be more important for the shorter term. The first essential is to establish the staffs of eminent scholars, writers and speakers, who will do the thinking, the analysis, the writing and the speaking. It will also be essential to have staff personnel who are thoroughly familiar with the media, and how most effectively to communicate with the public. Among the more obvious means are the following:TelevisionThe national television networks should be monitored in the same way that textbooks should be kept under constant surveillance. This applies not merely to so-called educational programs (such as “Selling of the Pentagon”), but to the daily “news analysis” which so often includes the most insidious type of criticism of the enterprise system.12 Whether this criticism results from hostility or economic ignorance, the result is the gradual erosion of confidence in “business” and free enterprise.This monitoring, to be effective, would require constant examination of the texts of adequate samples of programs. Complaints — to the media and to the Federal Communications Commission — should be made promptly and strongly when programs are unfair or inaccurate.Equal time should be demanded when appropriate. Effort should be made to see that the forum-type programs (the Today Show, Meet the Press, etc.) afford at least as much opportunity for supporters of the American system to participate as these programs do for those who attack it.Other MediaRadio and the press are also important, and every available means should be employed to challenge and refute unfair attacks, as well as to present the affirmative case through these media.The Scholarly JournalsIt is especially important for the Chamber’s “faculty of scholars” to publish. One of the keys to the success of the liberal and leftist faculty members has been their passion for “publication” and “lecturing.” A similar passion must exist among the Chamber’s scholars.Incentives might be devised to induce more “publishing” by independent scholars who do believe in the system.There should be a fairly steady flow of scholarly articles presented to a broad spectrum of magazines and periodicals — ranging from the popular magazines (Life, Look, Reader’s Digest, etc.) to the more intellectual ones (Atlantic, Harper’s, Saturday Review, New York, etc.)13 and to the various professional journals.Books, Paperbacks and PamphletsThe news stands — at airports, drugstores, and elsewhere — are filled with paperbacks and pamphlets advocating everything from revolution to erotic free love. One finds almost no attractive, well-written paperbacks or pamphlets on “our side.” It will be difficult to compete with an Eldridge Cleaver or even a Charles Reich for reader attention, but unless the effort is made — on a large enough scale and with appropriate imagination to assure some success — this opportunity for educating the public will be irretrievably lost.Paid AdvertisementsBusiness pays hundreds of millions of dollars to the media for advertisements. Most of this supports specific products; much of it supports institutional image making; and some fraction of it does support the system. But the latter has been more or less tangential, and rarely part of a sustained, major effort to inform and enlighten the American people.If American business devoted only 10% of its total annual advertising budget to this overall purpose, it would be a statesman-like expenditure.The Neglected Political ArenaIn the final analysis, the payoff — short-of revolution — is what government does. Business has been the favorite whipping-boy of many politicians for many years. But the measure of how far this has gone is perhaps best found in the anti-business views now being expressed by several leading candidates for President of the United States.It is still Marxist doctrine that the “capitalist” countries are controlled by big business. This doctrine, consistently a part of leftist propaganda all over the world, has a wide public following among Americans.Yet, as every business executive knows, few elements of American society today have as little influence in government as the American businessman, the corporation, or even the millions of corporate stockholders. If one doubts this, let him undertake the role of “lobbyist” for the business point of view before Congressional committees. The same situation obtains in the legislative halls of most states and major cities. One does not exaggerate to say that, in terms of political influence with respect to the course of legislation and government action, the American business executive is truly the “forgotten man.”Current examples of the impotency of business, and of the near-contempt with which businessmen’s views are held, are the stampedes by politicians to support almost any legislation related to “consumerism” or to the “environment.”Politicians reflect what they believe to be majority views of their constituents. It is thus evident that most politicians are making the judgment that the public has little sympathy for the businessman or his viewpoint.The educational programs suggested above would be designed to enlighten public thinking — not so much about the businessman and his individual role as about the system which he administers, and which provides the goods, services and jobs on which our country depends.But one should not postpone more direct political action, while awaiting the gradual change in public opinion to be effected through education and information. Business must learn the lesson, long ago learned by labor and other self-interest groups. This is the lesson that political power is necessary; that such power must be assidously (sic) cultivated; and that when necessary, it must be used aggressively and with determination — without embarrassment and without the reluctance which has been so characteristic of American business.As unwelcome as it may be to the Chamber, it should consider assuming a broader and more vigorous role in the political arena.Neglected Opportunity in the CourtsAmerican business and the enterprise system have been affected as much by the courts as by the executive and legislative branches of government. Under our constitutional system, especially with an activist-minded Supreme Court, the judiciary may be the most important instrument for social, economic and political change.Other organizations and groups, recognizing this, have been far more astute in exploiting judicial action than American business. Perhaps the most active exploiters of the judicial system have been groups ranging in political orientation from “liberal” to the far left.The American Civil Liberties Union is one example. It initiates or intervenes in scores of cases each year, and it files briefs amicus curiae in the Supreme Court in a number of cases during each term of that court. Labor unions, civil rights groups and now the public interest law firms are extremely active in the judicial arena. Their success, often at business’ expense, has not been inconsequential.This is a vast area of opportunity for the Chamber, if it is willing to undertake the role of spokesman for American business and if, in turn, business is willing to provide the funds.As with respect to scholars and speakers, the Chamber would need a highly competent staff of lawyers. In special situations it should be authorized to engage, to appear as counsel amicus in the Supreme Court, lawyers of national standing and reputation. The greatest care should be exercised in selecting the cases in which to participate, or the suits to institute. But the opportunity merits the necessary effort.Neglected Stockholder PowerThe average member of the public thinks of “business” as an impersonal corporate entity, owned by the very rich and managed by over-paid executives. There is an almost total failure to appreciate that “business” actually embraces — in one way or another — most Americans. Those for whom business provides jobs, constitute a fairly obvious class. But the 20 million stockholders — most of whom are of modest means — are the real owners, the real entrepreneurs, the real capitalists under our system. They provide the capital which fuels the economic system which has produced the highest standard of living in all history. Yet, stockholders have been as ineffectual as business executives in promoting a genuine understanding of our system or in exercising political influence.The question which merits the most thorough examination is how can the weight and influence of stockholders — 20 million voters — be mobilized to support (i) an educational program and (ii) a political action program.Individual corporations are now required to make numerous reports to shareholders. Many corporations also have expensive “news” magazines which go to employees and stockholders. These opportunities to communicate can be used far more effectively as educational media.The corporation itself must exercise restraint in undertaking political action and must, of course, comply with applicable laws. But is it not feasible — through an affiliate of the Chamber or otherwise — to establish a national organization of American stockholders and give it enough muscle to be influential?A More Aggressive AttitudeBusiness interests — especially big business and their national trade organizations — have tried to maintain low profiles, especially with respect to political action.As suggested in the Wall Street Journal article, it has been fairly characteristic of the average business executive to be tolerant — at least in public — of those who attack his corporation and the system. Very few businessmen or business organizations respond in kind. There has been a disposition to appease; to regard the opposition as willing to compromise, or as likely to fade away in due time.Business has shunted confrontation politics. Business, quite understandably, has been repelled by the multiplicity of non-negotiable “demands” made constantly by self-interest groups of all kinds.While neither responsible business interests, nor the United States Chamber of Commerce, would engage in the irresponsible tactics of some pressure groups, it is essential that spokesmen for the enterprise system — at all levels and at every opportunity — be far more aggressive than in the past.There should be no hesitation to attack the Naders, the Marcuses and others who openly seek destruction of the system. There should not be the slightest hesitation to press vigorously in all political arenas for support of the enterprise system. Nor should there be reluctance to penalize politically those who oppose it.Lessons can be learned from organized labor in this respect. The head of the AFL-CIO may not appeal to businessmen as the most endearing or public-minded of citizens. Yet, over many years the heads of national labor organizations have done what they were paid to do very effectively. They may not have been beloved, but they have been respected — where it counts the most — by politicians, on the campus, and among the media.It is time for American business — which has demonstrated the greatest capacity in all history to produce and to influence consumer decisions — to apply their great talents vigorously to the preservation of the system itself.The CostThe type of program described above (which includes a broadly based combination of education and political action), if undertaken long term and adequately staffed, would require far more generous financial support from American corporations than the Chamber has ever received in the past. High level management participation in Chamber affairs also would be required.The staff of the Chamber would have to be significantly increased, with the highest quality established and maintained. Salaries would have to be at levels fully comparable to those paid key business executives and the most prestigious faculty members. Professionals of the great skill in advertising and in working with the media, speakers, lawyers and other specialists would have to be recruited.It is possible that the organization of the Chamber itself would benefit from restructuring. For example, as suggested by union experience, the office of President of the Chamber might well be a full-time career position. To assure maximum effectiveness and continuity, the chief executive officer of the Chamber should not be changed each year. The functions now largely performed by the President could be transferred to a Chairman of the Board, annually elected by the membership. The Board, of course, would continue to exercise policy control.Quality Control is EssentialEssential ingredients of the entire program must be responsibility and “quality control.” The publications, the articles, the speeches, the media programs, the advertising, the briefs filed in courts, and the appearances before legislative committees — all must meet the most exacting standards of accuracy and professional excellence. They must merit respect for their level of public responsibility and scholarship, whether one agrees with the viewpoints expressed or not.Relationship to FreedomThe threat to the enterprise system is not merely a matter of economics. It also is a threat to individual freedom.It is this great truth — now so submerged by the rhetoric of the New Left and of many liberals — that must be re-affirmed if this program is to be meaningful.There seems to be little awareness that the only alternatives to free enterprise are varying degrees of bureaucratic regulation of individual freedom — ranging from that under moderate socialism to the iron heel of the leftist or rightist dictatorship.We in America already have moved very far indeed toward some aspects of state socialism, as the needs and complexities of a vast urban society require types of regulation and control that were quite unnecessary in earlier times. In some areas, such regulation and control already have seriously impaired the freedom of both business and labor, and indeed of the public generally. But most of the essential freedoms remain: private ownership, private profit, labor unions, collective bargaining, consumer choice, and a market economy in which competition largely determines price, quality and variety of the goods and services provided the consumer.In addition to the ideological attack on the system itself (discussed in this memorandum), its essentials also are threatened by inequitable taxation, and — more recently — by an inflation which has seemed uncontrollable.14 But whatever the causes of diminishing economic freedom may be, the truth is that freedom as a concept is indivisible. As the experience of the socialist and totalitarian states demonstrates, the contraction and denial of economic freedom is followed inevitably by governmental restrictions on other cherished rights. It is this message, above all others, that must be carried home to the American people.ConclusionIt hardly need be said that the views expressed above are tentative and suggestive. The first step should be a thorough study. But this would be an exercise in futility unless the Board of Directors of the Chamber accepts the fundamental premise of this paper, namely, that business and the enterprise system are in deep trouble, and the hour is late.Footnotes (Powell’s)Variously called: the “free enterprise system,” “capitalism,” and the “profit system.” The American political system of democracy under the rule of law is also under attack, often by the same individuals and organizations who seek to undermine the enterprise system.Richmond News Leader, June 8, 1970. Column of William F. Buckley, Jr.N.Y. Times Service article, reprinted Richmond Times-Dispatch, May 17, 1971.Stewart Alsop, Yale and the Deadly Danger, Newsweek, May 18. 1970.Editorial, Richmond Times-Dispatch, July 7, 1971.Dr. Milton Friedman, Prof. of Economics, U. of Chicago, writing a foreword to Dr. Arthur A. Shenfield’s Rockford College lectures entitled “The Ideological War Against Western Society,” copyrighted 1970 by Rockford College.Fortune. May, 1971, p. 145. This Fortune analysis of the Nader influence includes a reference to Nader’s visit to a college where he was paid a lecture fee of $2,500 for “denouncing America’s big corporations in venomous language . . . bringing (rousing and spontaneous) bursts of applause” when he was asked when he planned to run for President.The Washington Post, Column of William Raspberry, June 28, 1971.Jeffrey St. John, The Wall Street Journal, May 21, 1971.Barron’s National Business and Financial Weekly, “The Total Break with America, The Fifth Annual Conference of Socialist Scholars,” Sept. 15, 1969.On many campuses freedom of speech has been denied to all who express moderate or conservative viewpoints.It has been estimated that the evening half-hour news programs of the networks reach daily some 50,000,000 Americans.One illustration of the type of article which should not go unanswered appeared in the popular “The New York” of July 19, 1971. This was entitled “A Populist Manifesto” by ultra liberal Jack Newfield — who argued that “the root need in our country is ‘to redistribute wealth’.”The recent “freeze” of prices and wages may well be justified by the current inflationary crisis. But if imposed as a permanent measure the enterprise system will have sustained a near fatal blow.Followup: http://law2.wlu.edu/deptimages/Powell%20Archives/PowellSpeechResearchAOFESMemo.pdfHere is Bill Moyers take on it: The Powell Memo: A Call-to-Arms for Corporations | BillMoyers.com
- Home >
- Catalog >
- Business >
- Letter Template >
- Sample Letter Of Interest >
- Interest Letter For Volunteering >
- cover letter for volunteer work in schools >
- Faculty Absence Request Form Pdf